Posts Tagged: CogSci

Cognitive Science

Paper: Addition as interactive problem solving

These dual skills of manipulating the environment and processing the environment (…) allow us to reduce very complex problems to a series of very simple ones. (…) This is real symbol processing and, we are beginning to think, the primary symbol processing that we are able to do. Indeed, on this view, the external environment becomes a key extension to our mind.
McClelland, Rumelhart and the PDP Research Group (1986): Vol. 2, p. 46

[Copyright neth.de, 2001–2014]:

Hans Neth and Steve Payne (2001).

Addition as interactive problem solving. Paper presented at CogSci 2001.

Hansjörg Neth, Stephen J. Payne

Addition as interactive problem solving

Abstract:  Successful problem solving depends on a dynamic interplay of resources between agent, task, and task environment. To illuminate these interactions we studied how participants added a series of single-digit numbers presented on a computer screen. We distinguished between four different user interfaces, each implementing a different mode of interaction with the displayed addends: look only, point, mark, and move. By collecting and analysing complete interaction protocols we were able to integrate overall performance measures with fine-grained behavioural process data on the strategies engendered by the different user interfaces. We discovered reliable differences in the chosen sequences of addends, which can be understood in terms of the cost-benefit structures provided by the interactive resources of the user interfaces.

Keywords:  Embodied cognition, mental arithmetic, epistemic actions, complementary strategies, immediate interactive behavior (IIB).

Reference:  Neth, H., & Payne, S. J. (2001). Addition as interactive problem solving. In J. D. Moore & K. Stenning (Eds.), Proceedings of the 23rd Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 698–703). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Related:  Thinking by doing? | Immediate interactive behavior (IIB) | Arabic vs. Roman arithmetic | Taxonomy of actions | The cognitive basis of arithmetic | Interactive coin addition | The functional task environment

Resources:  Download PDF | Google Scholar

Paper: Searching for counterexamples

If it was so, it might be;
and if it were so, it would be;
but as it isn’t, it ain’t.
That’s logic.
Tweedledee (Lewis Carroll,
Through the Looking Glass and
what Alice found there, 1872)

[Copyright neth.de, 1999-2014]:

Hans Neth and Phil Johnson-Laird (1999).

The search for counterexamples in human reasoning.

Poster presented at CogSci 1999.

Hansjörg Neth, Philip N. Johnson-Laird

The search for counterexamples in human reasoning

Research question:  A major point of contention about human reasoning is whether or not individuals search for counterexamples to conclusions.  According to theorists who argue that the mind is equipped with tacit rules of inference, the decision that an argument is invalid depends on a failure to find a derivation leading from the premises to the conclusion (see e.g., Rips, 1994).  However, with this procedure, one can never be cer- tain that the space of possible derivations has been searched exhaustively.  Alternatively, reasoners may base their inferences on mental models (Johnson-Laird and Byrne, 1991).  This theoretical account rests on the semantic principle of validity: a conclusion is valid if and only if it allows for no counterexamples, i.e., possibilities in which the premises are true but the conclusion is false.  Hence, by constructing a counterexample, reasoners are able to know that an inference is invalid.

Method:  To search for a search for counterexamples, we carried out an experiment in which the participants had to evaluate eight inferences based on non-standard quantifiers.  Quite common in everyday life, such inferences call for a higher-order predicate calculus, which is incomplete.

Results:  A striking phenomenon was the participants’ spontaneous use of a variety of strategies.  In 80% of all trials, they constructed a single specific instance of the premises.  Typically, the participants constructed a diagram in which they tried to minimize the overlap between the given sets.  Indeed, every single participant came up with at least one counterexample.  Our study has shown (…) that logically naive individuals do spontaneously search for counterexamples for at least one sort of deduction.

Neth and Johnson-Laird (1999): Counterexample

Neth and Johnson-Laird (1999): The search for counterexamples in human reasoning.

Keywords:  Logic, thinking and reasoning, syllogisms with non-standard quantifiers, mental model theory, counterexamples.

Reference:  Neth, H., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1999).  The search for counterexamples in human reasoning.  In M. Hahn, & S. C. Stoness (Eds.),  Proceedings of the 21st Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (p. 806). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Related:   Suppression effects | Diploma thesis

Resources:  Download PDF | Google Scholar

Paper: Suppression effects

A conditional (…) is not a creature of constant hue, but chameleon-like,
takes on the colour of its surroundings: its meaning is determined
to some extent by the very propositions it connects
.
P.C. Wason and P.N. Johnson-Laird (1972), Psychology of reasoning: Structure and content, p. 92
Conditionals are acceptable in virtue of a number of different patterns of dependence (…)
If we have no pattern of dependence in mind, a primary object of our investigation
should then be to get one in mind.
D.H. Sanford (1989): If P, then Q: Conditionals and the foundations of reasoning, p. 196ff

[Copyright neth.de, 1999]:

Hans Neth and Sigi Beller (1999):

How knowledge interferes with reasoning: Suppression effects by content and context. Paper presented at CogSci 1999.

Hansjörg Neth, Sieghard Beller

How knowledge interferes with reasoning: Suppression effects by content and context

Abstract:  The suppression of logically valid inferences by the content or context of premises can be seen as an instance of knowledge having a detrimental influence on reasoning.  Although Henle (1962) has claimed that invalid deductions are due to additional premises drawn from background knowledge, current research on content effects ignores the methodological implications of this claim.  Elaborating on the suppression effect in conditional reasoning (Byrne, 1989), we present a knowledge-based approach that makes relevant features of background knowledge an integral part of the analysis.  After identifying the sufficiency and necessity of conditions as the type of knowledge mediating the effect, we construct and validate task materials independently from any assessment of reasoning (Experiment 1).  We then replicate and extend suppression effects in syllogism tasks (Experiment 2) and show that participants are able to couch their background knowledge in formally correct wordings (Experiment 3).

Keywords:  Logic, thinking and reasoning, conditional syllogisms, effects of knowledge, content, context.

Reference:  Neth, H., & Beller, S. (1999).  How knowledge interferes with reasoning: Suppression effects by content and context.  In M. Hahn, & S. C. Stoness (Eds.),  Proceedings of the 21st Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 468–473).  Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Related: Searching for counterexamples | Diploma thesis

Resources:  Download PDF | Google Scholar